close
test_template

The Connection Between Law and Morality

Human-Written
download print

About this sample

About this sample

close
Human-Written

Words: 1515 |

Page: 1|

8 min read

Published: Jan 8, 2020

Words: 1515|Page: 1|8 min read

Published: Jan 8, 2020

Table of contents

  1. Introduction
  2. Morality and Adjudication
  3. Internal Morality of Law
  4. Conclusion

Introduction

The Separability Thesis is a fragment of a normative legal positivist concept, where it emphasises that laws and morality are separate from one another. ‘John Austin indicated that ‘continuous of law is one thing, its advantages or disadvantages another’. For example, the law does not need moral authority to be a law as well as, if there is ‘law’ or not, the response is grounded exclusively on empirical verification. An interpretation that laws are established on social proofs. Legal philosophers have mainly absorbed on the query of whether morality and law are necessarily associated, the logical question is, ‘in what way are law and morality connected?’ Only some of the how law and morality are connected are of possible philosophical importance. There is at least two objections to this separability thesis. Hart asserts that there is no essential certainty that law imitates or fulfils clear requests of morality. Hart is recognised for his disapproval to his positivist forerunner, where he discards the ‘command theory’ and highlighting that law has numerous other fundamentals that make up its features. Similar to Hart, not all positivists precisely underline the separation thesis. Inclusive positivists claim that law does not have morality, though, in evident situations, it may occur. On the other hand, exclusive positivists do encourage the firm principle that laws and morality are different, rather, responses are to be originated in the bases of the laws. Joseph Raz dictates that there are no moral disagreements to be made from the law, legal authority is merely grounded on the bases of laws. Nonetheless, in this paper, I will rebut the statement that laws do have a morality which can be discovered within.

Morality and Adjudication

Judges who are confronted with hard cases, they alternate to the moral philosophies. Dworkin claims that judges appeal to moral values when they are confronted with hard cases. He does not consent that positivist assertion about laws merely contains rules. Two known qualities of Ronald Dworkin's philosophy of adjudication make an odd difficulty. Dworkin upholds that many events, containing most ‘hard’ cases, have ‘correct responses.’ In contradiction, Dworkin claims that to find that correct response, judges should benefit themselves of moral concerns and moral disagreement: a group's privileges follow from the principle that clarifies some important part of the previously established history and delivers the best defence for that institutional history as a subject of political morality.

In regards to Dworkin, there are three phases of adjudication. The first phase includes finding the applicable philosophies. The next phase includes a procedure of logically showing the situated principles of law. The last phase includes operating the law to the best appropriate case. In the hard cases, interpretation process would not apply at all, or if it does it would cease at the second stage because there will be no relevant principle to the situation to the best the fit the circumstances. For example, in the case of Riggs v Palmer, the offender sought to rely on the law to derive the land, the judge went throughout the informative phases to discover the applicable law and if the judge was to operate the law the outcome would have occurred to be ridiculous. Therefore, in the final informative phase, the judge utilises to determining the moral values. All of these cases exemplify that morality is to be discovered in the law, hereafter separability thesis is uncertain.

However, there is an apparent objection in the above disputes. The theory fails to tackle the general morality in the law. Dworkin’s proposal only includes utilising moral principles whilst judges are confronted with hard cases. Correspondingly, numerous legal events are understood from legal causes and most of the judges do not option to moral principles to resolves matters instead exactly obey the law. For instance, legal bases are obeyed by traffic courts instead of moral values. Similarly, there is no option to moral values when settlements are based on most of junior courts. The objection might settle the opinion that implementing moral values are only grounded on the High Court conclusions. Consequently, the concept is founded on a little measure of the cases in the law, does not deliver complete opinion if the law has moral domains or not.

Internal Morality of Law

Many understand Lon Fuller’s view on the internal morality of law as intended to comprehend in a way that law has the control to modify the kind of the purposes we have for performing: to permit redescribing an average directive as a moral condition. The fundamental assumption remains that the control to imitate the normative feature of what should be completed that law has is a purpose of the rules leading law-making. In the model, case laws are created merely if they are constructed having completely contented the eight standards. He considers them as moral necessities upon law-making, although which is indeed a debated statement. Conversely, some discuss them as essential moral restrictions on the procedure of law-making or as theoretical restrictions upon law it could assist us to reflect concerning what Fuller was concerned approaching if we consider the eight standards the internal morality of law.

Fuller claims that fundamental internal morality is originated when they encounter the standard of principles of legality. Subsequently, that regulations require to be universal, they are obligated to be spread, regulations necessitate to function, laws require to be transparent and reliable, stay away enacting laws where the agreement would be irrational, the permanency of the laws exclusive of common alterations, and matter of the law and enforceability should be consistent. Therefore, if these values are to be functional to the laws in the current legal method, regulations encounter the standards. For example, the regulation of not killing individuals. It can be persuasively reasoned that not to murder individuals is a usually appropriate rule. It is apparent and reliable with social standards, similarly, such law is very potential, therefore encounters the essential type of flourishing the public and defends them from danger. Fuller might have settled that Nazi Laws were no regulations at all as they did not have internal morality, in the Nazi Germany example of grudge cases. If separability thesis is factual, it would be debated that Nazi laws were certainly laws and it shall be difficult to sentence these laws exclusive of morality. Also, presume lawmakers present reconsidering rules for broadcasting attacking newspaper articles against the government. If the standard was to be functioned to this sort of law, it would surely collapse to encounter potential purpose of the law standard. Disappointment in consulting the standards would affect in a rule that is against public flourishing and not moral. Nevertheless, is it not the circumstance, regulations do balance the necessity of creating the separability thesis unenforceable.

A core objection can be elevated to the previous system is that it is very probable that a government might encounter all the recommended standards, and nevertheless attain a bad result. Fuller’s principles of legality are simply effective for lawmakers to attain their goals, the only method to accomplish moral claim of the regulations is when lawmakers have respectable purposes, Hart would claim. Similarly, Australian Nauru camp can be seen as a main visual of modern government obeying the regulation and the result is not moral. Correspondingly, this case deals with Austin’s Command Theory of law, which can be debated that an independent who has control may obey the course and yet do a bad act. The case of Nazi Germany, the sovereign, the individual in control obeyed the regulation and progressed his criminal arrangement. Hence, it can be decided that Fuller’s validity values do not grasp power except the lawmakers do not have morally respectable purposes and that numerous laws do not plan the infamous, therefore do have morality.

Conclusion

Law and morality are not different from one another. Morality is initiated within the laws, in addition to whilst judges are confronted with hard cases. Laws have a simple moral responsibility which is to develop the public and defend it from damages. Principles of legality by Fuller can be functioned throughout various diverse authorities to determine the morality of the law. For instance, Fuller’s value that laws necessitate being potential, which is a well-known moral standard that lawmakers are not to complete reflective laws. Hence, Fuller’s legality principles do create a comprehensive assertion about morality in the laws. Additionally, ‘principles of legality’ the counterclaim which converts as unacceptable whilst a government or sovereign has a bad purpose, which has no significance to how law and morality are different.

Get a custom paper now from our expert writers.

Moreover, moral principles are determined when judges are confronted with hard cases. Judges undergo phases of clarification in adjudication, therefore when hard cases arise they alternate to determining the moral standard to suit the condition. Which can be seen in the case Rigs v Palmer, courts were capable to determine the moral principles from the law. The counterclaim that hard case moral adjudication is only restricted to the minority of cases is groundless as well. The results from hard cases are obligatory and universal that are ranged downhill on to the lower courts.

Image of Dr. Charlotte Jacobson
This essay was reviewed by
Dr. Charlotte Jacobson

Cite this Essay

Philosophy of Law. (2023, January 12). GradesFixer. Retrieved December 8, 2024, from https://gradesfixer.com/free-essay-examples/philosophy-of-law/
“Philosophy of Law.” GradesFixer, 12 Jan. 2023, gradesfixer.com/free-essay-examples/philosophy-of-law/
Philosophy of Law. [online]. Available at: <https://gradesfixer.com/free-essay-examples/philosophy-of-law/> [Accessed 8 Dec. 2024].
Philosophy of Law [Internet]. GradesFixer. 2023 Jan 12 [cited 2024 Dec 8]. Available from: https://gradesfixer.com/free-essay-examples/philosophy-of-law/
copy
Keep in mind: This sample was shared by another student.
  • 450+ experts on 30 subjects ready to help
  • Custom essay delivered in as few as 3 hours
Write my essay

Still can’t find what you need?

Browse our vast selection of original essay samples, each expertly formatted and styled

close

Where do you want us to send this sample?

    By clicking “Continue”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy.

    close

    Be careful. This essay is not unique

    This essay was donated by a student and is likely to have been used and submitted before

    Download this Sample

    Free samples may contain mistakes and not unique parts

    close

    Sorry, we could not paraphrase this essay. Our professional writers can rewrite it and get you a unique paper.

    close

    Thanks!

    Please check your inbox.

    We can write you a custom essay that will follow your exact instructions and meet the deadlines. Let's fix your grades together!

    clock-banner-side

    Get Your
    Personalized Essay in 3 Hours or Less!

    exit-popup-close
    We can help you get a better grade and deliver your task on time!
    • Instructions Followed To The Letter
    • Deadlines Met At Every Stage
    • Unique And Plagiarism Free
    Order your paper now